1 Summary

As of 7pm 24 April, Sportsbet betting odds imply:

  • Labor to form the next government with 55.3% probability.

  • 14 seats changing hands in the House of Representatives; see section 3.4 below.

  • Labor leads in 77 seats.

  • Independents favourites in 3 seats: Clark, Indi, Warringah.

This analysis examines Sportsbet odds in various election betting markets for the 2022 Australian federal election.

We convert odds into implied probabilities of winning (IPOW) using a procedure explained in the Appendix.

In the tables and charts below, we express IPOWs as percentages.

2 Next government market

As of 7pm 24 April:

Result Price IPOW IPOW
(no long shots)
Labor 1.70 54.5 55.3
Coalition 2.10 44.1 44.7
Any Other 67.00 1.4 0.0

Time series:

3 House of Representatives seats

3.1 Expected seat counts

We compute expected seat counts by summing the seat-specific probabilities of winning implied by Sportsbet’s odds as at 7pm 24 April.

The second column of seat counts removes “long-shots”, where the implied probability of winning is less than 10%; we do so by setting the probability of these candidates/parties to zero and renormalizing the remaining non-zero IPOWs to sum to one in each seat. This focuses attention on differences between parties and candidates with more realistic prospects of winning.

The third column of counts shows where the indicated party has the highest IPOW.

Party Expected
Seats
Expected
Seats
(no long-shots)
Seats
where
favourite
ALP 70.0 76.0 77
GRN 5.6 2.0 1
IND 9.6 7.7 3
LNP 60.5 63.1 68
OTH 6.0 2.2 2
PHON 1.7 0.0 0

3.2 Seat-by-seat IPOWs

We remove long-shots (IPOWs < 10%) and renormalise the remaining IPOWS to sum to 100% in each seat:

## Warning: Values from `prob` are not uniquely identified; output will contain list-cols.
## * Use `values_fn = list` to suppress this warning.
## * Use `values_fn = {summary_fun}` to summarise duplicates.
## * Use the following dplyr code to identify duplicates.
##   {data} %>%
##     dplyr::group_by(lab, event, outcomes_collapsed) %>%
##     dplyr::summarise(n = dplyr::n(), .groups = "drop") %>%
##     dplyr::filter(n > 1L)

3.3 Relationship between IPOW and seat margins

With long-shot probabilities again set to zero, we examine the relationship between IPOWs and two-candidate preferred results in each seat, using 2019 results of notional results in the event of electoral redistributions since 2019.

Current Sportsbet prices are broadly consistent with the assumption of a 4 to 5 percentage point TCP swing from the Coalition to Labor. That is, IPOWs of 50% are around a 54-46 Coalition/Labor split of the 2019 or notional 2022 TPP vote.

Roll a mouse or pointing device over individual data points for more information.

3.4 Seats likely to change hands

The following 14 seats have candidates of incumbent parties with IPOWs of less then 50%:

4 Appendix

Australian bookmakers tend to use decimal odds, the return to the punter of a successful unit or one-dollar wager. In general, the more likely the event, the closer the decimals odds approach 1.00 from above; conversely, the less likely the event, decimal odds take on increasingly larger values.

If \(d = (d_1, \ldots, d_J)'\) are decimal odds over \(J\) mutually exclusive and exhaustive outcomes then the implied probability of event \(j \in 1, \ldots, J\) is conventionally recovered as

\[\begin{equation} p_j = \frac{1/d_j}{\sum_{k=1}^J 1/d_k} \tag{4.1} \end{equation}\]

In the context of elections, we refer to \(p_j\) as the implied probability of winning or IPOW for party or candidate \(j\).

This transformation of decimal odds into IPOWs can be rationalised as follows. Bookmakers set prices not merely as a function of their beliefs about outcomes, but also to lock in profits. The most telling case comes from observing that for coin tosses ahead of cricket matches, bookmakers typically offer prices of \(d\) = 1.91 or thereabouts for each of the two outcomes; more surprising is that gamblers participate in this market at all. This is a case where the actual probabilities held by both bookmakers and punters can be reasonably presumed to be 50-50 on each of the two outcomes. A fair price on a unit wager is therefore 2.00, with expected value of 1.00 = .5 \(\times\) 2.00 + .5 \(\times\) 0.

Observe that the fair price of \(d\) = 2.00 is simply the inverse of the probability of \(p\) = .5. This result generalises: fair decimal odds are simply the inverse of the probabilities of the corresponding events, or \(d = 1/p\) and conversely \(p = 1/d\).

But bookmakers prices can not be assumed to be fair. For the coin toss example, the bookmakers’ prices of less than the fair price of 2.00 reflect their profit margin. With decimals odds of \(d\) = 1.91, the bookmaker will lose 91 cents on each successful dollar wager, but keep $1.00 on each unsuccessful wager. This asymmetry in payouts with respect to equally likely events is the key to the adage that “the house always wins”. In this example the bookmaker has an expected yield of 4.5c cents per dollar waged.

Alternatively, applying the rule that probabilities are the inverses of the corresponding decimal odds, then with prices of 1.91 on both outcomes, the bookmaker’s apparent probabilities are 0.5236 for each outcome. This clearly violates the law of total probability (that the probabilities over the set of possible outcomes sum to one), in this case summing to 1.0471.

The apparent “extra probability” is known as the “over-round” or “vigorish”. Bookmakers prices therefore reflect at least two inputs: (1) probabilities about events; (2) profit margins (Cortis 2015). Let \(p_j\) be the bookmakers’ privately held probability of event \(j\). A profit-motivated bookmaker offers prices of \(d_j = 1/\pi_j\), where \(\pi_j = p_j(1+k_j)\) with \(k_j > 0\) the source of the bookmaker’s profits.

In the literature assessing the predictive value of betting markets, the conversion from decimal odds almost always assumes \(k_j\) is a constant \(k\) over all events \(j\), giving rise to the transformation

\[ \frac{1/d_j}{\sum_j 1/d_j} = \frac{\pi_j}{\sum_j 1/\pi_j} = \frac{p_j(1+k)}{\sum_j p_j(1+k)} = \frac{(1+k)\, p_j}{(1+k)\sum_j p_j} = p_j, \] as per equation (4.1).

Štrumbelj (2014) and Levitt (2004) survey cases where \(k_j\) might reasonably be expected to not be constant over outcomes \(j\); examples include information and skill asymmetries between bookmakers and punters and/or bookmakers seeking to counter insider-trading. Betting markets with large numbers of gamblers and bookmakers should generally drive these effects towards zero, resulting in small variability in \(k_j\) over alternatives, validating the mapping from odds to IPOWs in equation (4.1).

Of course, prior research suggests that seat-by-seat markets are thinly traded, and so we interpret IPOWs in these markets with appropriate caveats. Following my earlier work (Jackman 2015), one of the goals of this analysis in its post-election phase will be to assess the calibration of IPOWs with election outcomes.

References

Cortis, Dominic. 2015. “Expected Values and Variances in Bookmaker Payouts: A Theoretical Approach Towards Setting Limits on Odds.” The Journal of Prediction Markets 9 (1): 1–14.
Jackman, Simon. 2015. “All That Glitters: Betting Markets and the 2013 Australian Federal Election.” In Abbott’s Gambit : The 2013 Australian Federal Election, edited by Carol Johnson, Wanna, John, and Lee, Hsu-Ann. Canberra: ANU Press. https://doi.org/10.22459/AG.01.2015.09.
Levitt, Steven D. 2004. “Why Are Gambling Markets Organised so Differently from Financial Markets?” The Economic Journal 114 (495): 223–46. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0297.2004.00207.x.
Štrumbelj, Erik. 2014. “On Determining Probability Forecasts from Betting Odds.” International Journal of Forecasting 30 (4): 934–43. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ijforecast.2014.02.008.